Untethered in the Platonic Realm
  • What I Offer
  • Blog
  • About me
  • Contact
  • What I Offer
  • Blog
  • About me
  • Contact

Venice Summer School 2023

23/9/2023

0 Comments

 

The future of evolutionary-developmental systems biology

https://meetings.embo.org/event/23-evolution-venice
Every two years, I co-direct a theoretical summer school on topics related to evolutionary developmental and systems biology at the Centro Culturale Don Orione Artigianelli in Venice. My current partner in crime is philosopher of science James DiFrisco. Future editions of the school will be co-organized by us and Nicole Repina.
Since 2019, the school is funded by the European Molecular Biology Organization (EMBO) (in past years jointly with the Federation of European Biochemical Societies).

Picture
Centro Cultural Don Orione Artigianelli, Venice.
Since its first iteration in 2009, the summer school has become an established and highly valued institution in the field of evolutionary biology. It is targeted at early stage researchers (graduate students, postdoctoral researchers, and junior group leaders) interested in conceptual challenges and theoretical aspects of the field. Its participants not only include evolutionary theorists, but also empirical researchers from evolutionary developmental biology and other areas of  biology, computational and mathematical biologists, as well as a contingent of philosophers.
It is great to see that an increasing number of past participants are having a real impact on the field, publishing good theoretical work and contributing to urgently needed reflections and discussions on how to study both the sources and consequences of the variation that drives evolution by natural selection.
This year's edition of the summer school took place at Don Orione from August 21 to 25, 2023. Its focus, for a change, was not on a particular conceptual problem, but on the various challenges that face us moving forward in our field. For this purpose, we subdivided the program of the school into distinct themes, one each day:
On Monday, we discussed the role of genetic causation in complex regulatory systems, with contributions from James DiFrisco and Benedikt Hallgrímsson. While James criticized the gene-regulatory-network metaphor, examining how to embed the dynamics of gene expression in its tissue-mechanical context, Benedikt focused on the effect of genes on the evolvability of phenotypic traits, questioning many of our deepest assumptions (e.g. genes as regulators) in this context.
On Tuesday, we looked at the relationship of evolutionary developmental and systems biology with evolutionary genetics. Dani Nunes introduced methods used for mapping actual genetic variation within populations and between species, highlighting the problem that, in the end, we are still limited to examining a small number of candidate genes, while knowing full well that natural variation is highly polygenic (if not even omnigenic). Günter Wagner reminded us that "nothing in evolution makes sense except in the light of cell biology," focusing on the evolution of cell types and the role this plays in overcoming the homeostatic tendencies of the organism. Mihaela Pavličev looked at the many uses and limitations of the genotype-phenotype map metaphor in the context of developmental and physiological systems that span many levels of organization.
On Wednesday, the school focused on the use of dynamical systems modeling in the study of the genotype-phenotype map. Renske Vroomans introduced us to the methodology of evolutionary simulation, and how it can help us understand the origin of evolutionary novelties that lead to macro-evolutionary patterns. James Sharpe showed how data-driven dynamical models of regulatory and signaling networks in their native tissue context can reveal hidden homologies in the evolution of the vertebrate limb. Veronica Grieneisen, in turn, highlighted the importance of multi-scale modeling for understanding the properties of developmental processes beyond the genotypic level.
On Thursday, our school turned to organism-centered approaches to evolution. Graham Budd revisited George Gaylord Simpson's work on the tempo and mode of evolution, stressing the importance of rate differences and survivorship bias for the study of evolutionary patterns such as the Cambrian Explosion. Denis Walsh advocated an agential perspective on organism-level evolution that allows us to countermap the limitations of more traditional reductionist approaches. My own contribution grounded this approach in an organizational account of the organism, arguing that only organized systems (organisms) but not naked replicators can be true units of evolution.
On Friday, the last day of the course, we examined the role of technological versus conceptually driven progress in biology. Nicole Repina talked about the disconnect between 'omics' and other quantitative large-scale data sets and our ability to gain insights into the self-organizing capabilities and variability of cellular and developmental systems. As the final speaker of the course, Alan Love criticized the idea that progress in biology is predominantly driven by technological progress, argued for a broad conception of "theory" in biology, and highlighted the need to foreground its role in identifying problems across biological disciplines.
Morning lectures were complemented by intensive journal clubs and small-group discussions in the afternoons, plus an excursion to the (in)famous spandrels (pendentives, actually) of San Marco, and our equally (in)famous (and never-ending) evening discussions at Osteria all Bifora on Campo Santa Margherita.

Picture
This year's cohort of students and teachers.
In summary, this year's summer school touched on the following topics:
  • Evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) can be seen as a field defined by historical and sociological boundaries rather than around a particular set of problems and methods. Alternatively, it can be contextualized within the broader field that we call evolutionary systems biology, which is focused around the study of the sources of variation in evolutionary biology, across many levels of organization, from the molecular to the organismic.
  • Current theory in evolutionary developmental and systems biology falls short of providing a philosophically grounded or productive approach to the sources of variation, and does not integrate well into existing evolutionary theory. As an alternative to views centered around evolutionary synthesis, we suggest an approach based on the philosophy of multi-perspectival realism. On this view, a productive theory consists of an interconnected set of local models that are robustly supported in a given empirical domain.
  • This kind of pluralism is useful only if each and every perspective is solidly justified and put in relation to others, without striving to integrate all of them into a rigid overarching framework. Perspectives must perform useful conceptual work, such as providing unique explanations or making unique predictions. In this way, a perspectival approach gains higher accuracy, robustness, and broader explanatory power than any monolithic (and hence highly abstracted) theory.
  • In fact, the complexity and open-endedness of the sources of variation in evolution can be captured precisely by the fact that it affords a great number of valid but partial perspectives. These perspectives interact in non-trivial ways. Studying these interactions is what yields the most profound insight in our field, and most clearly reveals both use and limitations of individual perspectives.
  • This is useful, for instance, when examining our choices for model-building, which are currently not guided by any foundational theoretical principles. More data only increases the confusion induced by this lack of proper foundations. Simplification through idealization or abstraction induces further complications. For example, information-based approaches to biological system often lead to "physics-free models" (e.g. replicator-based models frequently used in evolutionary simulation), which would not work in any real-world setting.
  • This highlights the importance of including context into models of genetic regulatory systems, not only that of far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics and mechanobiology, but also the highly epistatic and polygenic background suggested by omnigenics. The pervasive and fundamental importance of such background conditions poses huge challenges to any reductionist empirical or modeling-based approach in biology, and evolutionary biology in particular.
  • Systems biology means we are looking at complex systems of interacting components, not only within a specific level or organization but across levels. The many mesoscales between genes and organisms matter! So does the overall organismic organization such multi-level regulatory systems are embedded in. We need theoretical approaches whose formalisms are not only adequate to the biological nature of the systems being studied, but are also grounded in robust philosophical principles. This poses a huge challenge for theoreticians in the field.
  • Last but not least, the study of biological regulation, at the metabolic, physiological, and developmental level, must be embedded in a comparative context. Only comparative biology can give us robust insights into which parts of a biological mechanism is funtionally important, and which is merely historically contingent (an accident of evolutionary history). Thus, the issues we have discussed during our course are not only important to evolutionary theorists, but should be known to any biological researcher.
Picture
The organizers of the school in action! Improvising their summary lecture on the fly...
All in all, we are looking back on a very successful edition of the school this year. The number of applications has been back up to pre-COVID levels, and feedback was overwhelmingly and gratifyingly positive. But most important of all: we greatly enjoyed, as we always do, to interact with the most talented and enthusiastic young individuals our field has to offer. We are very much looking forward to future editions of the summer school and will do everything we can to keep this wonderful institution going!
See you in Venice in 2025!
0 Comments

The Thing about Epistemic Humility

15/9/2023

0 Comments

 
Twice now, in the short span of one week, I've been reminded on social media that I should be more humble when arguing — that I lack epistemic humility.
Occasion 1: I was criticizing current practices of scientific peer-review, which systematically marginalize philosophical challenges to the reductionist-mechanistic status quo in biology. My arguments were labeled "one-sided," my philosophical work a mere "opinion piece," and I was accused of "seeing windmills everywhere," unable to reflect on my own delusions.
Occasion 2: I was reacting to the glib statement by a colleague (clearly intended to shut down an ongoing conversation) that "brains are strictly computers, not just metaphorically." This burst of hot air was not backed up by any deeper reasoning or evidence. It never is. When calling out his bullshit, I was reminded to "engage in good faith" and to "consider that I might be wrong."
These two situations are intimately connected: it is a sad fact that the large majority of biologists and neuroscientists today is not properly educated in philosophical thinking, and never ponders the philosophical foundations of their assumptions. The problem is: most of these assumptions are literally bullshit, a term I do not use as an insult, but in its philosophical sense, meaning "speech intended to persuade without regard for truth." These days, it seems to me, we often use bullshit even to persuade ourselves.
I've called the fuzzy conglomeration of ideas that make up the "philosophy" of contemporary reductionist life- and neuroscience naïve realism, and have discussed its problems in detail before (see also this preprint). Let's just say that it is philosophically unsound and totally outdated. Because of that, it has become a real impediment to progress in science.
Yet, despite all this, the zombie carcass of reductionist mechanicism (and its relative: computationalism) is kept standing behind a wall of silence, a lack of questioning ourselves, enforced by the frantic pace of our current academic research environment, which leaves no time for reflection, and a publication system that gives philosophical challenges to the mainstream ideology no chance to be seen or to be discussed in front of a wider audience.
This has been going on, getting increasingly and significantly worse, over the entire 25-year span of my research career. But no worries, I'll keep shouting into the void.
So, what about epistemic humility, then? Why would I think I have a point while everybody else is wrong? Well, the truth is that the accusations hurtled against me are deeply ironic. To understand why, we need to talk about a very common confusion concerning the question of when we ought to be humble. This is an important problem in our crazy times.
It is of utmost importance to be epistemically humble when building your own worldview, when considering your own assumptions. This is why I stick to something called naturalist philosophy of science. You can read up on it in detail here or here, if you are interested. In brief, it is based on the fundamental assumption that we are all limited beings, that our knowledge is always fallible, and that the world is fundamentally beyond or grasp. Still, science can give us the best (most robust) knowledge possible given our idiosyncrasies, biases, and limitations, so we'd better stick to the insights it generates, revising our worldview whenever the evidence changes. Naturalism is the embodied practice of epistemic humility.
At the heart of contemporary naturalist philosophy is scientific perspectivism. There are great books by philosophers Ron Giere, Bill Wimsatt, and Michela Massimi about it that are all very accessible to scientists. The basic point is this: you cannot step out of your head, you cannot get a "view from nowhere," not as an individual and not as a society or scientific community. Our view of the world will always be, well, our view, with all the problems and limitations that entails. Scientific knowledge is constructed, but (and this is the crux of the matter here), it is not arbitrary.
Perspectivism is not "anything goes," or "knowledge is just discourse and power games." It does not mean that everybody is entitled to their own opinion! My philosopher friend Dan calls this kind of pluralism, where anyone's view is as good as anyone else's, group-hug pluralism. Richard Bernstein calls it flabby, contrasting it with a more engaged pluralism: it is very well possible, at least locally and in our given situation, to tell whether some perspective connects to reality, or whether it completely fails to do so.
And this is exactly where we should not be humble. Even though my personal philosophy is fundamentally based on epistemic humility, I can call bullshit when I see it. The prevalent reductionism and computationalism in biology and neuroscience, propped up by an academic and peer-review system designed to avoid criticism, self-reflection, and open discussion, are hollow, vacuous constructs with no deeper philosophical meaning or foundation. That's why its proponents almost always shy away from confrontation. That's how they hide their unfounded assumptions. This is how they propagate their delusional worldview further and further.
And delusional it is. Completely detached from reality. To explain in detail why that is will take an entire book. The main point is: I have carefully elaborated arguments for my worldview. It may be wrong. In fact, I've never claimed it is right or the only way to see the world. I'm a perspectivist after all. It would be absurd for me to do so. But I call out people who do not have any arguments to justify their philosophical assumptions, yet are 100% convinced they are right. These people are trapped in their own model of the world. It is not epistemic humility to refrain from calling them out. It is just group-hug pluralism.
The problem with group-hugs right now is that reductionism and computationalism are very dangerous worldviews. They are not just the manifestation of harmless philosophical ignorance on behalf of some busy scientist. They are world-destroying ideologies. This may sound like hyperbole, but it isn't. Again, it'll take a whole book to lay out this argument in detail. But the core of the problem is simple: these philosophies treat the world as if it were a machine. This is not an accurate view. It is not a healthy view. It is at the heart of our hubris, our illusion that we can control the world. It is used to justify our exploitative self-destructive modern society. It urgently needs to change.
This change will not come from being nice to the man-child, the savant idiot, the narrow-minded fachidiot, who is the one that is not ready or willing to engage the world with humility. The problem is not that I do not understand their views or needs. I understand them all too well: they want to hide from the real world in their feeble little mental models of the world. And they're out to destroy.
Treating the world as a machine helps them pretend the world is their oyster, that they are in control. They loathe unpredictability, mysteries, unintended side-effects, even though all these things undeniably laugh in their faces, all of the time. It is only their bullshit ideology that enables them to pretend these obvious things do not exist. And they are very powerful. They are the majority in our fields of research. They run the tech industry. They influence our politicians and create the AI that is disrupting our lives and societies. We must fight them, and their delusions, if humanity is to survive.
You know what? Screw epistemic humility in this context. Their ideology does not make sense. It's bullshit, and ours is an existential fight. We cannot afford to lose it. It is courage not humility we need right now. Just like the paradox of tolerance, this is one of the great conundrums of our time: we must defend epistemic humility with conviction against those who do not understand it, who do not want it, and who will never have it.
0 Comments

    Johannes Jäger

    Life beyond dogma!

    Free-floating systems thinker & natural philosopher.

    Anti-fragilist extemporanian metamodernist.

    Open science, open society & open living.

    Deliberate & explore.

    Archives

    September 2023
    March 2023
    February 2023
    October 2022
    September 2022
    March 2022
    January 2022
    November 2021
    November 2020
    October 2020

    Categories

    All
    Academic Politics
    Agency
    Artificial Intelligence (AI)
    Artificial Life (ALife)
    Arts & Science
    Dynamical Systems
    Evolution
    Naturalism
    Philosophical Biology
    Philosophy Of Biology
    Science Communication
    Synthesis
    THE ZONE
    Wissenskunst

    RSS Feed

Proudly powered by Weebly